What The State Is Not-Rothbard

WHAT THE STATE IS NOT

“The State is almost universally considered an institution of social service.
Some theorists venerate the Stateas the apotheosis of society; others regard it as an amiable, though often inefficient, organization for achieving social ends; but almost all regard it as a necessary means for achieving the goals omankind, a means to be ranged  against the “private sector” and often winning in this competition of resources. With the rise of democracy, the identification of the State with society has been redoubled, until it is common to hear sentiments expressed which violate virtually every tenet of reason and commonsense such as, “we

are the government.” The useful collective term “we” has enabled an ideological camouflage to be thrown over the reality of political life. If “we
are the government,” then anything a government does to an individual is not only just and untyrannical but also “voluntary” on the part of the individual concerned. If the government has incurred a huge public debt which must be paid by taxing one group for the benefit of another, this reality of burden is obscured by
saying that “we owe it to ourselves”; if the government conscripts a man, or throws him into jail for dissident opinion, then he is “doing it to himself” and, therefore, nothing untoward has occurred. Under this reasoning, any Jews murdered by the Nazi government were not murdered; instead, they must have “committed suicide,” since they were the government (which was democratically chosen), and, therefore, anything the government did to them was voluntary on their part. One would not think it necessary to belabor this point, and yet the overwhelming bulk of the people hold this fallacy to a greater or lesser degree.

We must, therefore, emphasize that “we” are not the government; the government is not “us.” The government does not in any accurate sense “represent” the majority of the people.1 But, even if it did, even if 70 percent of the people decided
to murder the remaining 30 percent, this wouldstill be murder and would not be voluntary suicide on the part of the slaughtered minority.2 No
organicist metaphor, no irrelevant bromide that “we are all part of one another,” must be permitted to obscure this basic fact. If, then, the State is not “us,” if it is not “the human family” getting together to decide mutual problems, if it is not a lodge meeting or country club, what is it? Briefly, the State is that organization in society which attempts to maintain a monopoly of the use of force and violence in a given territorial area; in particular, it is the only organization in society that obtains its revenue not by voluntary contribution or payment for services rendered but by coercion. While other individuals or institutions obtain their income by production of goods and services and by the peaceful and voluntary sale of these goods 

and services to others, the State obtains its revenue by the use of compulsion; that is, by the use and the threat of the jailhouse and the bayonet.3 Having used force and violence to obtain its revenue, the State generally goes on to regulate
and dictate the other actions of its individual subjects. One would think that simple observation of all States through history and over the globe would be proof enough of this assertion; but the miasma of myth has lain so long over State activity that elaboration is necessary.

—————–

1 We cannot, in this chapter, develop the many problems and
fallacies of “democracy.” Suffice it to say here that an individual’s

true agent or “representative” is always subject to that individual’s orders, can be dismissed at any time and cannot act contrary
to the interests or wishes of his principal. Clearly, the “representative” in a democracy can never fulfill such agency functions,
the only ones consonant with a libertarian society.
2 Social democrats often retort that democracy—majority
choice of rulers—logically implies that the majority must leave
certain freedoms to the minority, for the minority might one
day become the majority. Apart from other flaws, this argument obviously does not hold where the minority cannot
become the majority, for example, when the minority is of a
different racial or ethnic group from the majority

3 Joseph A. Schumpeter, Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy (New York: Harper and Bros., 1942), p. 198.
The friction or antagonism between the private and the
public sphere was intensified from the first by the fact
that . . . the State has been living on a revenue which was
being produced in the private sphere for private purposes and had to be deflected from these purposes by
political force. The theory which construes taxes on the
analogy of club dues or of the purchase of the service of,
say, a doctor only proves how far removed this part of
the social sciences is from scientific habits of mind.
Also see Murray N. Rothbard, “The Fallacy of the ‘Public Sector,”’ New Individualist Review (Summer, 1961): 3ff.

Anatomy of the State, pp. 9-12, Murray N. Rothbard

SEE:

https://mises.org/library/anatomy-state